Corporate social responsibility: Doing well
by doing good
Oliver Falck 1, Stephan Heblich ⁎
University of Passau, Innstraβe 27, D-94032, Passau, Germany
Abstract Saving the rain forest from yet another palm oil plantation would certainly
garner a company favorable attention from environmentalists, but how would its
shareholders react? In this article, we show that by strategically practicing corporate
social responsibility (CSR), a company can ‘do well by doing good’; in other words, it
can make a profit and make the world a better place at the same time. CSR is regarded
as voluntary corporate commitment to exceed the explicit and implicit obligations
imposed on a company by society's expectations of conventional corporate behavior.
Hence, CSR is a way of promoting social trends in order to enhance society's basic
order, which we define as consisting of obligations that cover both the legal framework
and social conventions. Due to globalization, companies are now less constrained by
society's basic order than they have been in the past. Because different countries have
different laws and standards, there are more ways to get away with less than ideal
behavior in the quest for greater and greater profits. Nearly everyone agrees that this
is not a good thing, but what can be done? Via this article, we offer an understanding of
CSR that could be the answer. Herein, we contend that practicing CSR is not altruistic
do-gooding, but rather a way for both companies and society to prosper. This is
especially true when CSR is conceived of as a long-range plan of action.
© 2006 Kelley School of Business, Indiana University. All rights reserved.
KEYWORDS
Corporate social
responsibility;
Stakeholder;
Shareholder;
Principal–agent;
Society's basic order
1. CSR as win–win strategy
Can companies enhance society's basic order, and, if
so, is this advantageous for them? With this question
in mind, it is the goal of this article to take a closer
look at the opportunities and frontiers of a strategic,
profit-maximizing use of corporate social responsibility (CSR). In doing so, CSR is regarded as voluntary
corporate commitment to exceed the explicit and
implicit obligations imposed on a company by
society's expectations of conventional corporate
behavior.
Society's basic order consists of both the legal
framework and social conventions; it is always a
representation of the society's prevailing ideas and
opinions. New, emerging social trends cannot pass
into society's basic order per se; in fact, they need
to be promoted so that they might establish over
time. Companies can support this procedure and in
doing so, gain profits at the same time. Porter and
⁎ Corresponding author.
E-mail addresses: [email protected] (O. Falck),
[email protected] (S. Heblich).
1 Present address: Institute for Economic Research, Poschingerstraβe 5, D-81679 Munchen, Germany.
www.elsevier.com/locate/bushor
0007-6813/$ - see front matter © 2006 Kelley School of Business, Indiana University. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.bushor.2006.12.002
Business Horizons (2007) 50, 247–254Kramer (2002) call this win–win situation strategic
philanthropy.
In the United States, the interrelation between a
company's social commitment and its profitability
has been of scientific concern since at least the
1970s. Among scholars, Margolis and Walsh (2001)
and Orlitzky, Schmidt, and Rynes (2003) present a
broad review of the existing literature, arriving at
the same conclusion that the market rewards enterprises' social activities. CSR can thus be considered an efficient management strategy (Baron,
2003), and can be a crucial factor in the company's
success. Short-term actions such as donating money
for social purposes or sponsoring popular events,
however, are not the most effective means of
attaining this goal. Rather, effective CSR is usually
a long-term proposition. The practice of CSR is an
investment in the company's future; as such, it must
be planned specifically, supervised carefully, and
evaluated regularly. Used well, it is a way of actively
contributing to the society's basic order and, in
doing so, enhancing the company's reputation. From
a supply-side perspective, a good reputation is necessary to attract, retain, and motivate quality employees. From a demand-side perspective, a good
reputation increases the value of the brand, which,
in turn, increases the company's goodwill.
The possibilities for CSR actions depend heavily
upon a country's prevailing economic policy. Until
recently, CSR was primarily a phenomenon found in
the United States and the United Kingdom; continental Europe had not yet expressed much interest
in the concept. These different attitudes are a reflection of differing economic views: Great Britain
under Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher leaned
toward the American, liberal economic policy
prone to deregulation, whereas most of continental
Europe relied on a relatively high density of
regulation. If CSR is understood as a voluntary
corporate commitment that helps establish social
trends and institutional demands, the differences in
its level of importance for countries become evident.
As long as society's basic order binds companies to
comply with social demands, there is no necessity for
CSR. Not until society's basic order is unable to
represent social trends in an appropriate way will
CSR come into play.
Because European interest in CSR is a relatively
recent phenomenon, there are not in existence very
many continental European studies on the subject.
Increasing globalization and the use of global public
goods, along with the declining influence of national
institutions, however, is making CSR a more vital
issue in this part of the world. The national basic
order is becoming less important for companies.
Multinational enterprises face a plurality of different institutional conditions. In the absence of global
governance, which could introduce and establish a
supranational institutional framework, companies
can force a race to the bottom concerning regulatory regimes. Civil society, however, reacts with
hostility to such behavior; scandals such as that
involving Nike's sweatshops are illustrative. Therefore, cost savings in the short run need to be balanced against the potential risk to the company's
goodwill in the long run. It would be in their own
self-interest if companies would consider filling this
regulatory gap, rather than exploiting it.
The goal of this article is to assess strategic use of
CSR. We begin with a short historical summary of the
scientific debate over the term CSR. This background
facilitates better understanding of how CSR works and
illustrates that the practice does not necessarily
conflict with a company's economic well-being. In
fact, CSR often turns out to give a company an advantage. If a company realizes early on that a certain
social trend is gaining ground, it can act quickly to
take advantage of the situation by establishing itself
at the forefront of an issue that may become of major
public interest. For example, consider a scenario in
which the public becomes alarmed at the effects
caffeinated beverages have on the behavior of young
children. An alert and aware company that produces
such beverages could come out with a line of decaffeinated drinks, accompanied by a targeted
advertising campaign stressing the healthy aspects
of its product, and thus perhaps garner the public's
favor and an edge on the competition. The later a
company jumps on the bandwagon of a new trend, so
to speak, the less chance it has of becoming a leader
in the field or having much influence on the direction
of future regulation; put another way, the sooner a
company acts, the more influence it will have.
Accordingly, there is an incentive to act pro-actively
so as to gain a first-mover advantage. We will show
how social trends can be classified in such a way that
it is possible, using our proposed managerial decisionmaking process, to devise a win–win strategy to take
advantage of them. Finally, frontiers for the strategic
use of CSR are briefly discussed.
2. CSR in the course of time
Within the scientific literature, the term CSR was
first formalized by Bowen (1953), who argued in a
normative way that “it refers to the obligations of
businessmen to pursue those politics, to make
those decisions, or to follow those lines of actions
which are desirable in terms of the objectives and
values of society” (p. 6). A decade later, several
authors, including Davis (1960), Fredrick (1960),
248 O. Falck, S. HeblichMcGuire (1963), and Walton (1967), undertook
further development of the concept.
Notably, these authors, like Bowen before them,
refer only to ‘businessmen’. In 1967, Davis (1967)
finally enlarged the definition of CSR to include
institutions and, thus, enterprises. This was a crucial development, as to that point, use of the term
businessmen implied that an enterprise's owner was
also its manager, and thus bore the cost of every
social commitment personally. When CSR is expanded to include enterprises in their own right as legal
entities, however, the attribution of costs is not so
easy. In the case of a manager-led enterprise, for
example, the legal representatives of the enterprise, the managers, do not bear the costs of social
conduct; instead, they decide to take these actions
in their role as agents of the principals. This caused
Nobel Prize winner Milton Friedman (1962, 1970) to
fundamentally reject corporate social commitment.
From Friedman's point of view, managers in a free
economic system are obliged by contract to shareholder value; it is their primary task to maximize the
value of the enterprise. To this end, resources are
put to their best possible use and employed efficiently (which, according to classic economist Adam
Smith, best serves society as a whole). Managers'
actions are bound only by legal guidelines: the
economic rules. Commitment beyond legal requirements to general social interests is in breach of this
postulate, as there are no corresponding gains; thus,
such commitment should not be undertaken. Shareholder value is the only value to be maximized. If
managers want to work toward the betterment of
society, they should do so as private individuals at
their own expense, not as agents of their principals
and at their principals' expense (Friedman, 1970).
Friedman's basic assumption is the best possible
legal framework including completely assigned
property rights. External effects are ruled out by
definition. Therefore, the relevant question is not
whether an enterprise behaves in a socially desirable way, but whether existing legal requirements
provide incentives that cause enterprises to so act.
In other words, the important thing is not that
enterprises or individuals can assume responsibility, but that society's basic order has been designed
to cause the desired conduct. Due to these assumptions, there is no need for CSR in Friedman's
approach.
In reality, however, the assumption of a perfect
basic order is no longer valid. There are several factors that hinder its accomplishment. To begin with, it
must be understood that the design of current institutions is the result of a reaction to social needs, but
the delay between a change in social preferences and
an accordant institutionalization creates a regulation
gap. Filling this gap is sometimes more easily accomplished by companies than by governing entities.
As stated by Kofi Annan (2001) in a speech at the
American Chamber of Commerce, “Business is used to
acting decisively and quickly. The same cannot always
be said of the community of sovereign States. We
need your help—right now.”
Furthermore, due to increasing global sourcing,
enterprises are no longer subject to just one national
regulation, but are now confronted with various laws
and standards. As no world government exists, much
less one with adequate authority to sanction, there
is no binding legal framework on a supranational
level. Therefore, global market failures, especially
global external effects, can no longer be adequately
internalized.
In the absence of a perfect basic order, enterprises, particularly those multinational in nature,
can contribute to closing this regulation gap. Such
socially desirable conduct is not in conflict with
Friedman's presumption of profit maximization if:
(1) an enterprise views its individual commitment as
a long-term investment, or (2) all enterprises agree
on closing the regulation gap, making it a collective
commitment. In fact, a company's active role in
designing society's basic order leads to an adjustment of Friedman's implicit assumption of a perfect
basic order. In reality, there are external effects
that are not yet internalized, and Freeman's stakeholder theory approach provides the theoretical
framework to consider them.
Inhisseminalbook,StrategicManagement:A Stakeholder Approach, Freeman (1984) argued that the
”
shifts in traditional relationships with external groups
such as suppliers, customers, owners and employees,
as well as the emergence and renewed importance of
government, foreign competition, environmentalists,
consumer advocates, special interest groups, media
and others, mean that a new conceptual approach is
needed.” (p. 27)
This insight was the impetus behind Freeman's
stakeholder theory approach, which focuses on the
enterprise's external environment. Under this framework, anyone who might affect the business objective
and anyone who might be affected by its realization is
considered a stakeholder. Thus, society can be divided into clusters of different stakeholders by considering their interrelation with the company (e.g.,
shareholders, employees, strategic partners, suppliers, NGOs). According to the stakeholder theory approach, consideration of externalities and their
impact on stakeholders is critical to the company's
current and future success.
In order to make sure that this is achieved, CSR
can be strategically used to deal with the identified
Corporate social responsibility: Doing well by doing good 249stakeholders' claims. Management can employ CSR
as a prescriptive instrument in making plans that
will satisfy both the stakeholder and shareholder
approaches.
Fig. 1 illustrates the interrelation between
Friedman's (shareholder) approach and Freeman's
(stakeholder) approach, and introduces strategic
CSR into the relationship. Awareness of how all
three interrelate will help solve the win–win
puzzle: How can management identify and classify
social trends and plan corresponding strategic CSR
actions?
3. Solving the win–win puzzle
In attempting to solve the win–win puzzle, management needs to answer the question of which
stakeholders should be considered and, correspondingly, how much is at stake. These queries
can be satisfied by employing a multi-stage
process. As illustrated in Fig. 2, the decisionmaking process is initiated by a social trend. At
its inception, a trend is a social claim of unknown
size. Thus, the first task of strategic planning is to
evaluate the trend. Is it merely the claim of a
marginal group and liable to disappear quickly, or is
it possibly a claim of great public interest that will
become increasingly important? If government does
not react to a trend of broad public interest, the
company might be able to step in and address the
public's concern. The decision as to whether the
company should act must be based on an evaluation
of the opportunities and threats involved. A costbenefit analysis calculating the expected net
present value of the future cash flow would likely
be appropriate in making this decision. The
Figure 1 CSR: Theory-based management implications.
Figure 2 Planning process of strategic CSR action.
250 O. Falck, S. Heblichprocedure portrayed in Fig. 2 is a template for the
decision-making process.
Once a given trend has been evaluated, it must be
determined whether any of the company's stakeholders are involved or interested in it. If not, the
company should remain disengaged. If, however,
stakeholders are involved or interested, the claim
could have either direct or indirect effects on the
company. In such a case, management should deal
with the trend, assigning it priority appropriate to the
interested stakeholder's importance. Stakeholder
importance is determined by the stakeholder's influence on the company's cash flow. To evaluate and thus
be able to prioritize a stakeholder's importance, the
influence of all known stakeholders needs to be
mapped regarding their potential to interfere with
the company's cash flow. As illustrated in Fig. 3, this
leads to three different categories of stakeholders.
Stakeholders in the first category are known as
key stakeholders. This group includes all actors
that have a direct connection to the company and
can interfere significantly with the company's
current and expected cash flow. Accordingly, they
are the ones that need to be considered when calculating the expected net present value of the CSR
action. Key stakeholders are evaluated only once in
a specific context, after which their status is fixed
until the relationship changes fundamentally. The
volatility of the key stakeholders' expected cash
flow is low. This group includes, inter alia, the most
important suppliers, as well as major clients and
crucial employees.
Members of the second group are known as
emerging stakeholders. They do not have a current
direct connection to the enterprise's cash flow and
do not influence the expected net present value.
This situation can change rapidly, however, and
management needs to keep an eye on this group in
case some of its members suddenly become key
stakeholders. The volatility of the emerging stakeholders' expected cash flow is high; thus, this group
must be evaluated regularly. This group includes,
among others, suppliers that might gain influence in
the future, NGOs dealing with sensitive issues, and
politicians with the power to change the institutional framework.
Minor stakeholders make up the third group.
These stakeholders cannot interfere with the
company's cash flow in the medium-term, and as
such, although management needs to be aware of
them, it does not have to pay them much attention.
This group's expected cash flow volatility is low.
Management's decision criterion is the expected
net present value of the social investment. If this
value is positive, the investment should be undertaken. In making the investment decision concerning
the new social trend, it might be possible to transfer
the key stakeholders' contributions to the cash flow
from one context to another. This would leave a
need only to reevaluate the emerging stakeholders'
contributions, something which should be done
regularly in any case. For these reasons, the decision
will not take much time or incur much expense.
Depending on what is at stake, the investment
can be either an individual or a collective commitment. The company should choose a strategic action
of an individual commitment type if the claim can
be met by the company itself without any risk of
Figure 3 Management target priority.
Corporate social responsibility: Doing well by doing good 251opportunistic behavior on the part of competitors.
We call this an exclusive stake. This behavior is
strategic because the goal is to attain a first-mover
advantage (Jones, 1995). The enterprise that undertakes and leads a socially desirable action can
improve its reputation among customers, and thus
secure or expand its market share (Werther &
Chandler, 2005). The enterprise's action may also
prompt new social standards that serve as entry
barriers for potential competitors.
Migros, Switzerland's largest retail chain, is a good
example of a company that successfully chose
strategic action of the individual commitment type.
With supermarkets located in Switzerland, France,
and Germany, and exporting products to Austria, the
United Kingdom, and the United States, Migros, in
2002, committed itself to a standard for palm oil
production. One of the most important oils on the
world market and steadily growing in demand, palm
oil is an important raw material in the production of
margarine, washing agents, soap, and cosmetics.
Unfortunately, increased palm oil production historically came at the cost of lost rain forest acreage. The
revolutionary palm oil standard introduced by Migros,
however, guarantees responsible sourcing because
the company will not buy palm oil produced from
plantations that have been established at the expense
of the rain forest. Introducing this standard paid off
for Migros — twice! First, Migros won a UN award for
its action. Second, and even more important, the
company became an outrider in the global consumer
goods industry and thus gained influence. In championing this cause, Migros initiated a Round Table on
Sustainable Palm Oil (RSPO), and its standard has now
become the global standard.
As a means of overcoming collective problems, a
single enterprise's individual commitment is a risky
investment that will be successful only if it does not
lead to a competitive disadvantage in the long run. If
the individual enterprise's activities weaken its competitive position, competitors will be quick to take
advantage and, down the road, the enterprise will
either be forced to conform to the competitors'
standard of behavior or leave the market. No social
improvement will occur in this situation. Collective
commitment has to take the place of individual
commitment.
Structural action should be undertaken when a
collective commitment is required. It would not be
rational for an individual enterprise to take action;
rather, a collective action must be undertaken, something that is effected by and affects all competitors
equally. The action could lead to a concerted initiative to establish appropriate institutions or a voluntary, collective commitment to a common code of
conduct by several enterprises of a market segment.
Because all competitors (in the ideal case) are subjected to this code, there are no, at least no ruinous,
distortions of competition. For example, consider the
issue of corruption. If corruption (i.e., bribery) is
endemic in a certain industry, it would be nearly
suicidal for a single company in that industry to commit itself to a code of conduct not permitting any use
of bribery. Structural action would be needed to
change this situation and make it possible for the
industry as a whole to avoid great expense (i.e., stop
paying the bribes). According to the World Bank,
corruption adds at least 10% to the common costs of
doing business in many parts of the world. One of the
most popular initiatives supporting collective commitment is the UN Global Compact, by which enterprises commit themselves to respect 10 rules in the
fields of human rights, work, environment, and corruption. The free-rider problem, which is inherent
in such situations, can be minimized by nonpolitical
social organizations that monitor compliance with the
code of conduct and thus act as watchdogs (Werther &
Chandler, 2005).
Both structural action and strategic action are
ways of practicing strategic CSR. If the actions move
into the mainstream of society, they may become part
of society's basic order, either as explicit, legal
standards or as implicit, socially desired standards.
Of course, it is possible that, over time, implicit social
standards can become a part of the legal framework.
Martin (2002) provides a detailed description of this
process. Essential is that once an action becomes part
of society's basic order, it is established in the public
mind as such.
Hence, CSR can be viewed as part of the dynamic
process of discovery described by Hayek (1978). Society's basic order will always be imperfect, or incomplete, as it only reflects prevailing social opinion.
Developments to come (i.e., trends) cannot be foreseen and dealt with in advance. However, the way
social trends are made a part of the social order (that
is, by government intervention or self-regulation) can
be influenced and managed, and it is in this aspect
that companies have an opportunity to do well by
doing good.
4. Principal-agent hurdles
Taking the above into consideration, it becomes
obvious that the theory of stakeholders is, in the
long run, nothing but a shareholder value approach. The theory of stakeholders formalizes and
categorizes challenges the company needs to meet
if it wishes to pursue a long-term corporate
strategy. This is generally the default strategy of
owner-led companies. As the same person is both
252 O. Falck, S. Heblichmanager and owner, there is no principal–agent
conflict. Accordingly, businessmen usually follow a
long-term strategy and stakeholder claims are
considered per se.
The situation is a little different for manager-led
companies, but even here a long-term approach to
stakeholder management can be viable. The main
problem will be the incentive structure. If managers
are paid on a short-term performance basis, they will
necessarily act in a short run manner so as to
maximize their compensation, which will conflict
with the long-term goal of effective and profitable
stakeholder management. Social investment might
have a different expected net present value for
owners than it does for managers. If managers are
short-term oriented, they will have a higher individual discount rate. Accordingly, the expected net
present value is more likely to be negative and the
investment will not be made. With a change in compensation scheme, however, CSR can be integrated
into manager-led companies to their benefit, and
thus to society at large. This point is corroborated by
Tirole (2001), who contends that the stakeholder
society is best served by flat remuneration structures,
meaning fixed salaries without performance-oriented
incentive structures. Different studies back Tirole's
postulation empirically. For example, there appears
to be a connection between variable performancebased compensation and earnings management problems or accounting fraud.
If wage restructuring is not practicable, a more
feasible and less radical solution to this problem is the
use of equity-based long-term incentives (e.g., stock
options or restricted stocks). Stock options allow
managers to purchase a certain amount of stock at a
fairly long-term point in the future at a preset strike
price. Restricted stocks require a certain length of
time to pass or a given target to be met before they
can be sold. However, to avoid the possibility of yet
again setting up a less-than-optimum incentive
structure, there are several issues that must be
considered when using these long-term incentive
instruments. Among others:
• Managers need to have their ‘skin in the game’
(De Ruiter & Souër, 2005); in other words, they
must have a stake in the company. Stocks or options should not be granted as a bonus, but
instead be part of the basic compensation so
that managers either purchase them with their
own money or through exchange programs. This
will make managers responsible for the consequences of their decisions, good or bad.
• The restrictions placed on stocks or options need
to be chosen carefully. It is not enough to simply
set a fairly long-term vesting period; there need to
be constraints on the period before the stocks can
be sold or the options can be executed. Otherwise,
the problems that accompany a short-term orientation are merely shifted to the future.
• As equity-based incentive schemes could create
earnings management problems and lead to
accounting fraud, executives must be monitored
(for example, by the supervisory board). In this
vein, it should be noted that transparent compensation schemes make such monitoring easier.
So-called ‘target long-term incentives’ are a nonequity-based remuneration scheme that can be used
to short circuit short-term oriented management, as
well. This type of incentive compensation is granted
for fulfilling certain long-term performance-based
goals. However, finding and agreeing on adequate
targets that meet the final goal of long-term profit
maximization will not be without difficulty.
The pros and cons of these different incentive
schemes will need to be evaluated carefully before
implementation. The challenge for companies will
be to appropriately calibrate incentive awards with
performance outcomes, particularly for long-term
incentive programs. Apple's latest problems with
backdated stock options reflect the ongoing need for
creative action. In doing so, principal-agent hurdles
can be reduced and management's behavior can be
more closely aligned with the owner's goal of longterm profit maximization.
5. It can work
In conclusion, we believe that strategic practice of
CSR will involve a long-term shareholder value approach, which implies a long-term view of profit
maximization, as well. In the case of manager-led
companies, this will make necessary a change in
incentive structure so that the manager does well by
doing good. If it is a company's goal to survive and
prosper, it can do nothing better than to take a longterm view and understand that if it treats society
well, society will return the favor.
References
Annan, K., (2001). Secretary-General urges United States business
leaders to take concerted action against ‘unparalleled nightmare’ of AIDS. Retrieved July 21, 2006, from http://www.un.
org/News/Press/docs/2001/sgsm7827.doc.htm
Baron, D. (2003). Business and its environment. Upper Saddle
River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Bowen, H. (1953). Social responsibility of the businessman. New
York: Harper and Row.
Davis, K. (1960). Can business afford to ignore social responsibilities? California Management Review, 2(3), 70−76.
Corporate social responsibility: Doing well by doing good 253Davis, K. (1967). Understanding the social responsibility puzzle:
What does the businessman owe to society? Business Horizons,
10(4), 45−50.
De Ruiter, H., & Souër, J., (2005). An investor's view on executive
compensation plans. Corporate Social Responsibility Newsletter, 8–15. Retrieved August 7, 2006, from http://www.abp.nl/
abp/abp/vermogensbeheer_en/images/CSR%20Newsletter%
20External%20August%202005_tcm22-27532.pdf
Fredrick, W. (1960). The growing concern over business responsibility. California Management Review, 2(4), 54−61.
Freeman, E. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman.
Friedman, M. (1962). Capitalism and freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Friedman, M. (1970). The social responsibility of business is to
increase its profits (pp. SM17). New York Times Magazine,
13 September.
Hayek, F. A. (1978). Competition as a discovery procedure. In F. A.
Hayek (Ed.), New studies in philosophy, politics, and economics
(pp. 179−190). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Jones, T. (1995). Instrumental stakeholder theory: A synthesis
of ethics and economics. Academy of Management Review,
20(2), 404−437.
Margolis, J., & Walsh, J. (2001). People and profits? The search for
a link between a company's social and financial performance.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Martin, R. (2002). The virtue matrix: Calculating the return on
corporate responsibility. Harvard Business Review, 80(3),
69−75.
McGuire, J. (1963). Business and society. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Orlitzky, M., Schmidt, F., & Rynes, S. (2003). Corporate social and
financial performance: A meta-analysis. Organization Studies, 24(3), 403−441.
Porter, M., & Kramer, M. (2002). The competitive advantage of
corporate philanthropy. Harvard Business Review, 80(9),
48−58.
Tirole, J. (2001). Corporate governance. Econometria, 69(1), 1−35.
Walton, C. (1967). Corporate social responsibilities. Belmont,
CA: Wadsworth.
Werther, W., & Chandler, D. (2005). Strategic corporate social
responsibility as global brand insurance. Business Horizons,
48(4), 317−324.
254 O. Falck, S. Heblich